Wednesday, September 21, 2011

The Whim of the Nose: Of How Expectations are Fulfilled, or Not


In Nikolai Vasilievich Gogol’s The Nose, Major Kovalev wakes up one morning, stretches his arms and reaches out for a hand-mirror kept on the table near his bed. He meant to inspect a pimple that had broken out on his nose the night before. He starts from the right side of his face, notices his right ear in the mirror, the corner of his eye and his disheveled hair. Moving his face leftwards, he stops with a gasp. He witnesses an absence. To his utter astonishment there is nothing but a flat patch on his face where the nose should have been. There is no nose! In his shaken state, he examines his face further left. He sees everything else as expected, his left ear, his eyes, his mouth. But instead of fulfillment of the perceptual anticipations associated with the nose, he encounters only disappointment. He rubs his eyes, washes his face and pinches himself to ensure that he is not still asleep. But the nose continues to evade him.

We have here a case of absence — one where expectation is dramatically violated. It remains unfulfilled, generating a perceptual disappointment. Four observations are striking:

OBSERVATION 1. Any absence presumes a prior presence, i.e., a case of normal perception. The absence of the nose necessitates that the nose had once been where it isn’t now.
OBSERVATION 2. This prior presence (normal perception) is the cause of anticipation. Having repeatedly seen the nose every time Kovalev looked at his face in the mirror, he had an expectation to see it again.
OBSERVATION 3. In the case of perceptual negation these anticipations are disappointed. So when Kovalev took the mirror in his hand this time and did not find his nose, he was left aghast.
OBSERVATION 4. Absences are not absolute in the sense of pure nothing. In the inspection of his face, Kovalev encounters a partial unfulfillment. In the place of the nose is now a flat patch of skin and apart from the nose, the face presents no contradiction to his expectation.

The question now is: what triggers the failure of anticipation. In other words, what is the justification for and source of perceptual negation (experiential absence). This is the problem that concerns us, and I attempt to construct what a Husserlian answer to this would be. The emphasis in this treatment is on experiential or perceptual negation as a cognitive act rather than negation associated with propositions. This will involve a comprehensive survey of the character of a ‘normal’ perception which will lead us to the cases of what I call ‘non-normal’ (negative) perception. Husserl, in Experience and Judgment (1997 [1939]) broaches the question of negative judgments. These are dealt with in a more rigorous manner in Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis (2001). Following an examination of the case of the missing nose through the four observations listed above, we will encounter the mystery of the source and justification of absence itself. On a close examination, we will find that the locus of absence is not consciousness although it is consciousness which experiences it.

In the course of this discussion some terms will be used frequently: expectations, anticipations, protentions, fulfillment, un-fulfillment, disappointment, negation, absence. Of these, the first three are roughly used as synonyms and I define them as future orientations of consciousness with respect to an object. Fulfillment can be understood as the affirmation of these orientations in experience. The last four are once again near synonyms and are to be characterised as the opposite of fulfillment, i.e., the experience of something other than expected.

First, we broach the question of what is the nature of (NORMAL) perception for Husserl. Perception is the unfolding of an aspect of the object and a manifold of such appearances constructs the unity of sense. It proceeds in a flow of series of phases, with each of these phases synthesized to compose the unity and harmony of the perceptual object which is thereby originally constituted. In the act of perception, what is genuinely presented is one particular aspect of the object. Yet there is a facade of the object being given in its entirety. The object in perception is something more than what is genuinely perceived. But the peculiarity of perception is that it is of the nature of a pretension. It poses to realize something that it never can since all that is revealed in a single act of perception is one particular aspect/phase of an object.

External perception is a constant pretension to accomplish something that, by its very nature, it is not in a position to accomplish. (Husserl 2001: 39)

If perception is only given in phases, it is implicit that an object can never be fully known. The object is not given at once in full and there always remains the possibility of perceiving aspects other than previously perceived. In this sense, there can never be a closure or a complete determination.

The transitions of appearances following one after the other are all in dynamic displacement, enrichment and impoverishment. The object appearing constantly new, constantly different, is constituted as the same in these exceedingly intricate and wondrous system of intention and fulfillment that make up the appearances. But the object is never finished, never fixed completely. (Husserl 2001: 50)

Having said that perception of an object is actually nothing more than a series of phases, we must ask, what generates this illusion of unity and completeness of an object. In the perception of one aspect, there is an implicit consciousness of other aspects, which are not immediately visible. These exist as co-present — as part of the horizons of possibility of the object as retained in consciousness — and give unity to the object experience.

To take an example from Husserl, in the perception of a table, what we actually (genuinely) have is the view of the table ‘from some particular side’. But obviously that is not all that there is to the table, the table has still other sides. It has ‘a non-visible back side, it has a non-visible interior; and these are actually indexes for a variety of sides, a variety of complexes of possible visibility’ (Husserl 2001). This remarkable feature is central to perceptual experience. The other immediately non-visible sides of the table are co-present in the act and this gives a sense of unity in the perception of a ‘table’.  These co-present sides await their fulfillment in subsequent acts of perception.

In moving from a side that is given, to one that is not immediately given ‘now’ we move from fullness to emptiness, i.e., from something known, ‘given in flesh’ to something that is not yet so given. The movement from fullness to emptiness (in moving away from given-ness) is not in the direction of ‘nothing-ness’. This emptiness seeks to be fulfilled and anticipations are laden with the desire to determine an object more and more closely within the pre-figuring of an intuitively given framework. Expectations are a product of empty intentions whose possibilities are thus pre-figured. The actualization of anticipations (protentions) bestows fullness to what was empty. Yet with each instant of fulfillment there is a fading away of the aspect prior to the new perspective and it gradually becomes completely invisible, though held in retention. In this sense, there is a movement also in the opposite direction – from emptiness to fullness. Emptiness and fullness, concealment and projection thus have a dynamic relation, each moving towards the other in acts of perception.

Continually progressing fulfillment is at the same time a continually progressing emptying (Husserl 2001: 45).

Though there is a seeming fullness of consciousness in the act of perception, there exists a horizon of empty intentions waiting to be fulfilled. In perception, an anticipation which was previously only co-present becomes actual. At the same time there is a whole range of other co-present profiles waiting to be fulfilled. The object is presented not only by means of what is given, but also by means of what is not given, but possible — and this is the range of empty horizons. Fulfillment in the ‘now’ instant is the sign of a valid act of perception without any annulment, an affirmative perception of self giving. This is what we call a case of normal perception.

In all cases of normal perception, there is a unity of the object which manifests in spite of the wholeness of object being given in a non-genuine manner. The object is never grasped in its entirety and there is always a horizon of possibilities — possibilities of determining more closely.

In the normal case of perception, all fulfillment progresses as the fulfillment of expectations. These are systematized expectations, systems of rays of expectations which, in being fulfilled, also become enriched; that is, the empty sense becomes richer in sense, fitting into the way in which the sense was prefigured (Husserl 2001: 64).

Further,
Where there is no horizon, where there are no empty intentions, there is likewise no [synthesis of] fulfillment (ibid.: 108).

Therefore in every perceptual given-ness, there is a part which is familiar by virtue of its immediately being present and a part which is now unfamiliar (thus only co-present and not present) but may manifest as a possible perception. Through the series of aspect viewings there is a synthesis and what remains constant is the object, though not genuinely given in the act itself. The fulfillment associated with anticipations is concomitant with a yet closer determination of the object.

When we perceive a tree from the front, and wanting to know it better, draw nearer to it and now perceive it in new perceptions; by determining the tree more closely, we also have a fulfilling confirmation. Meanwhile, every external perception harbours its inner and outer horizons, regardless the extent to which perception has the character of self-giving; this is to say, it is a consciousness that simultaneously points beyond its own content. In its fullness it simultaneously points into an emptiness that would only now convey a new perception (Husserl 2001: 108).

To sum up (a) genuine perception proceeds in phases (b) yet there is a unity of perceptual object (c) because other aspects of the object are co-present (by virtue of the horizon of empty intentions) in the act of perception (d) nevertheless there is always a possibility of determining an object more closely.

Now having spoken of normal perception, we attempt to determine what is ‘NON-NORMAL’. In this manner we shall understand the nuances of perceptual negation. If Kovalev had woken up that morning and his anticipation associated with his nose had not failed, we would have had a case of normal perception. However what we are presented with now is a situation where we meet a failure, a negation — an absence, namely of the nose.

Negation is the failure of anticipation. It manifests when there is a disappointment with respect to the ‘now’ instant, i.e. the immediate moment of perceptual experience given to consciousness. Concordance is not a necessary feature of consciousness (with respect to perception) and this is manifested in the disappointment of anticipations, where the synthesis of fulfillment is held in scrutiny.

[S]uppose that we have observed a ball uniformly red; for a time the course of perception continues in such a way that this apprehension is harmoniously fulfilled. But now, in the progress of the perception, a part of the back side, not seen at first, is gradually revealed; and in opposition to the original prescription, which ran ‘uniformly red, uniformly spherical’, there emerges a consciousness of otherness, which disappoints the anticipation: ‘not red, but green’, ‘not spherical but dented’ (Husserl 1997).

Our experience of a rotating red ball fulfills the associated anticipation through the uniformity and continuity of its colour, shape, etc. throughout acts of perception. If however, a part of it were to be revealed as green instead of red and dented instead of spherical, the original anticipation is disappointed and it would be a case of perceptual negation.

To review the observations with which we began:

A negative perception however presumes that a normal perception (this is red, this is a ball/here is a nose) has already taken place, one which was unhindered and against whose background the negation manifests as a negation now (this is not red, this is not a ball/there is no nose) (OBSERVATION 1). The constitution of the object precedes its modification into a negation. It is thus parasitical on the affirming perception and may be seen as a modification of it.

When Kovalev begins to look at his face and first sees his right profile without having noticed the absence yet, implicit in his act of perception (of the face) is the nose, as co-present. It is an expectation that awaits fulfillment as he moves his face leftwards. What gives rise to this expectation is the ubiquity of the nose in all his normal perceptions until the moment he finds it missing (OBSERVATION 2). The perception of an aspect of the face lies within a general framework of sense – of what is the range of possibility of a face. This in Husserl’s term would be a ‘pre-figuring’ which determines the horizon of possibility. Yet this horizon of possibility cannot be conceived of in a vacuum. It must have an experiential basis, a precedence — a previous instance.  Only such an experiential basis would guarantee the possibility of re-identification such that what was once an object of perception can be evoked again and empty retentions can be filled up. In this sense, the possibility of recognition is not closed by the arrival of a fresh aspect. In spite of the absence of the nose, Kovalev does not fail to recognize the face – but there is a renewed perception of it. 

The fact that a re-perception, a renewed perception of the same thing is possible for transcendence characterizes the fundamental trait of transcendent perception, alone through which an abiding world is there for us, a reality that can be pregiven for us and can be freely at our disposal (Husserl 2001: 47).

The nature of perceptual cognition is such that it is inalienable from the desire for the realization of that which is anticipated. Disappointments then manifest due to non-realization of anticipation. The desire to find the nose on looking at the mirror must be a product of previous encounters. In Kovalev’s case this desire remains unfulfilled — he is disappointed (OBSERVATION 3).

Yet, this unfulfillment is not absolute. This can be understood in two related ways: (a) The absence does not entirely challenge the general criterion of intelligibility of lived experience. In other words, the absence of the nose does not disable Kovalev from cognizing the event – however absurd it may be. (b) The perception of absence lies within a unity of experience.  Kovalev perceives the face still — the absence of the nose on the face. In moving from right to left, there is a continuity of the experiential object – an aspect of which appears otherwise than expected. This unity is a product of the very structure of consciousness: ‘retention—now—protention’. As defined earlier, retention refers to the presentation of the perceptual act (of a phase) which is retained in consciousness even though it is no longer immediately present. Protention is presentation of that which is hitherto not given, but is yet to be perceived, thus embodying that which is expected. Retentional consciousness enables a pre-figuring of the empty horizons of perception such that it is inalienably associated with anticipations. 

In spelling out negation of anticipations, Husserl always speaks of fulfillment as partial. Partial fulfillment grants to experience the unity necessary for the act to maintain its flow, and as such there cannot be a complete non-fulfillment.  The absence of the nose does not constrain the unfolding of perceptual experience, of the face as a whole. But the perception now is not of the nose but of something else, a flat patch (OBSERVATION 4). The lived experience does manifest as continuous, but it appears to be other than expected (a flat patch and not the nose), thereby calling for an abrupt break. There is a substratum which is the body of change, of becoming otherwise, of alteration. The substratum working as the general framework persists throughout the act of perception giving unity of the act.

The conflict between contrary determinations (amid what is anticipated and what is presented) results in the institution of a new and altered perceptual sense. Not only does the sense of the presented object get altered, but intentions associated with it and the structure of now possible anticipations also gets modified. The origin of negation is in the pre-predicative realm of receptive experience. Green superimposes itself on the empty red-intention (a flat patch superimposes itself on the nose) thereby altering the substratum given in the original perception – giving it a new sense, and crossing out the anticipated sense. In the unfolding of perception, a sense is either affirmed (when fulfilled) or renewed (when unfulfilled).

To sum up, normal unobstructed original object-constitution must precede negation. This original constitution is carried out in a series of apperceptive apprehensions which are held in retention and thus generate expectation. Negation is a case of modification, which is essentially of the nature of a superimposition due to a case of conflicting intentions directed against each other. So what is fundamental to negation is the displacement and substitution of one sense (old sense) by another (new sense). Yet this annulment is never absolute but concerns itself with a limited range.

To return to the Nose, let us examine two possibilities: (a) absence as external event, without its locus in consciousness (b) absence as a modification of an intending consciousness. In other words, absence could either be a whim of the nose (as external to consciousness) or a whim of (an intending) consciousness. Either the nose walked off in the middle of the night or it had gone missing by trick of Kovalev’s own intentions. There is some absurdity in the second case, where a consciousness simultaneously expects X and intends not-X. For this reason, by admitting the possibility of perceptual negation, one necessitates withdrawal from a reality that is purely submerged and justified by consciousness. In both cases, no doubt it is consciousness which experiences the perceptual negation. But it seems that the source and justification of negation cannot be derived from consciousness. The notion of externality comes with a force the moment one desires to construe what triggered a disappointment. It is perhaps for this reason that Husserl’s descriptions of the constitution of perceptual sense carry an underlying assertion: that to constitute is not to create. Rather it is the condition of the possibility of experience and knowledge.

David Hume in pleading the case of habit asserted the essential unjustifiability of our beliefs about the external world. Being accustomed to the manner in which experience has proceeded in the past we have the expectation for a similar future. That the sun shall rise every morning is an inductive generalization from our experience of sun having risen every morning. Yet such an experience must always be probabilistic in nature. One cannot be absolutely certain about its claims, there might be an abrupt denial. Interestingly, such a denial come as a completely alarm to the experiencing subject. Habit has to have an empirical basis. The Nose presents one such case of perceptual denial. It proves that the nature of reality is ultimately contingent and the subject’s construal of an object’s horizon of possibility cannot obstruct a denial. In fact the horizon of possibility extends with every disappointment — perhaps a little with the green dented rear-side of the ball and a great deal more with a missing nose! In this sense, the main role of negation is to push the limit of the actual world.

To answer the question with which we began, what must trigger the failure of an anticipation, the answer can only be the contingent character of nature — the whim of the nose — and thereby of perceptual experience. The pre-figurings in the empty horizons waiting to be fulfilled, might not be fulfilled precisely because consciousness cannot determine and ensure a fulfillment. The external, one hand, determines what consciousness must anticipate. On the other, it is also responsible for whether the anticipated will be fulfilled or not. While perceptual experience is essential to consciousness and the locus of its strength, perceptual fulfillment is only its desire, and could be construed as the Achilles’ heel, a territory over which consciousness cannot have any real power, yet it continues to yearn for it.

References
Bernet, Rudolf. 2005. ‘Is the Present Ever Present? Phenomenology and the Metaphysics of Presence’, in Rudolf Bernet, Donn Welton and Gina Zavota (eds), The Nexus of Phenomena: Intentionality, Perception and Temporality, pp. 273-98. London: Routledge.
Brough, John. 2005. ‘The Emergence of an Absolute Consciousness in Husserl’s Early Writing on Time-Consciousness’, in Rudolf Bernet, Donn Welton and Gina Zavota (eds), The Nexus of Phenomena: Intentionality, Perception and Temporality, pp. 247-72. London: Routledge.
Cunningham, Suzanne. 1985. ‘Perceptual Meaning and Husserl’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 45(4): 553-66, http://www.jstor.org/stable/2107564 (accessed 15 January 2010).
Drummond, John J. 2005. ‘On Seeing a Material Thing in Space: The Role of Kinaesthesis in Visual Perception’, in Rudolf Bernet, Donn Welton and Gina Zavota (eds), The Nexus of Phenomena: Intentionality, Perception and Temporality, pp. 192-204. London: Routledge.
———. ‘The Structure of Intentionality’, in Rudolf Bernet, Donn Welton and Gina Zavota (eds), The Nexus of Phenomena: Intentionality, Perception and Temporality, pp. 31-60. London: Routledge.
Huemer, Wolfgang. 2003. ‘Husserl and Haugel and on Constitution’, Synthese, 137(3): 345-68.
Husserl, Edmund. 1970. Logical Investigations. London: Routledge and K. Paul.
———. 1990. Phenomenology of Internal Time Consciousness, trans. J. B. Brough. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
———. 1997 [1939]. Experience and Judgment. Illinois: Northwestern University Press.
———. 2001. Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis: Lectures on Transcendental Logic, ed. Anthony J Steinbock. London: Kluwer.
Kim, Sang-Ki. 1976. The Problem of the Contingency of the World in Husserl's Phenomenology. Amsterdam: B. R. Gruner.
Krysztofiak, Wojciech. 1992. ‘Phenomenology, Possible Worlds and Negation’, Husserl Studies, 8: 205-20.
Mohanty, J. N. 1954. ‘“Object” in Husserl’s Phenomenology’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 14(3): 343-53,   http://www.jstor.org/stable/2104106 (accessed 15 January 2010).
———.  2005. Husserl’s Concept of Intentionality, in Rudolf Bernet, Donn Welton and Gina Zavota (eds), The Nexus of Phenomena: Intentionality, Perception and Temporality, pp. 3-30. London: Routledge.
Moran, Dermot and Timothy Mooney (ed.) 2002. The Phenomenology Reader. London: Routledge.
Murphy, Richard T. 1965. ‘Husserl and Pre-Reflective Constitution’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 26(1): 100-105.
Sokolowski, Robert. 1970. The Formation of Husserl’s Concept of Constitution. The Huague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Zahavi, Dan. 2005. ‘Inner Time-Consciousness and Pre-Reflective Self Awareness’, in Rudolf Bernet, Donn Welton and Gina Zavota (eds), The Nexus of Phenomena: Intentionality, Perception and Temporality, pp 299-324. London: Routledge.

Silika Mohapatra is doctoral researcher at the Department of Philosophy, University of Delhi and was formerly visiting researcher at the Department of Philosophy, University of Ottawa (2010). She completed her BA (2007) and MA (2009) in philosophy from St. Stephen's College, Delhi. Her research interests include classical metaphysics, phenomenology, philosophy of technology, post-human studies and the ethics of self and society. She is the co-editor of Indian Political Thought: A Reader (London: Routledge, 2010).  

No comments:

Post a Comment